Aprohibitionism:
A Possible Alternative
By dott. Andrea
Michelazzi
Translation by
Catherine Dry
Before explaining what I
mean by Aprohibitionism, I would like to outline a few historical, social and
economic trends concerning the phenomena of addiction in order to clarify the
idea of Aprohibitionism.
To begin, it is important to note that since the end
of the sixteenth and the beginning of the seventeenth centuries drugs have played
a progressively more important role in Western and Westernized society. During this same historical period, Western
society changed from a mercantile-based system to a capitalistic one. Furthermore, the development of a
capitalistic society was closely linked to the increase of the use and abuse of
drugs. These drugs had different
mind-altering effects, different potential levels of toxicity and different
capacities for inducing addiction. Today, millions of people use, and are
addicted to, various drugs including cannabis, tobacco, cocaine, alcohol,
amphetamines and ecstasy. Other
substances that are often not explicitly considered as drugs, such as
psycho-pharmaceuticals and even food, often acquire the same addictive
qualities as the aforementioned drugs. Furthermore,
video-dependency, pornophilia and perhaps even some sexual habits are examples
of other behaviors that share similarities with the characteristic behaviors of
drug addiction. The progressive
development of the phenomena of dependency and addiction, which I have briefly
outlined here, cannot be merely chance
A closer look at the social context of the historical
period helps to clarify these trends. The
Enlightenment, the exaltation of Reason, the commodification of goods and the division
and mechanization of work have clearly produced a society which, other than
being dependent on money and consumption, is also more dependent in a general understanding of the word. This understanding of “dependent” includes
the aforementioned kinds of dependencies.
In a society dominated by Reason, there is always an expulsion of all
things that are contrary to Reason. Foucault’s notion of Reason and unReason
can be applied to this idea and may help to understand the presence of
addiction and addictive behaviors in our society. This expulsion is followed by the inevitable, and subtly cunning,
return into the social fabric of the values of unReason. Addiction and addictive behaviors can be the
manifestation of the return into society of the values that are contrary to
Reason. These values, therefore, can be
also understood as a kind of consubstantiation because they become an integral
part of the society that had explicitly excluded them before. The system of capitalism evolves and
different kinds of abuse evolve with it.
The political economy can no longer be understood according to classical
terms; the referential value of goods (also understood as the worth of a
commodity) no longer has a significant meaning in the system. Because the referential value of goods is
stripped of any significant meaning, a confusion ensues and the structural
value (the value of the commodity) becomes increasingly more exalted. Related to this “new economy,” drug abusers
and addicts turn to stimulants that give a sense of “security.”
Just as the division of work evolves and becomes
specialized with the development of mechanization, so the alienation of the
worker due to his commodification becomes something similar to
dispossession. Now the machine controls
the function and pace of the worker or even displaces him entirely. At the same time, the understanding of goods
as a fetish changes. A commodity
becomes a fetish when its value is defined by analyzing the value of the
process used to produce it. With this evolution
of capitalism, the commodity is no longer a fetish but rather becomes the
subject of fascination; the object is now transformed into the subject. This is what Jean Baudrillard would classify
as “obscenity” and is the current, post-modern phase of capitalism.
With this evolution in mind, we can now return to the
discussion of addiction and addictive behavior. Echoing Karl Marx’s famous dictum, “religion is the opium of the
people,” paradoxically, opium, during the early development of capitalism, can
be thought of as a kind of religion. Today,
chemical ecstasy has replaced opium and can be considered also as a kind of new
religion of the people. If psychiatric
disease represented a heavy blow to production based on work division, today, hardship
connected to drug dependence represents a heavy blow to reproduction based on
work mechanization.
The criminalization and the too often violent methods
of treatment and management of psychiatric patients can be compared to the
punishment and treatment of drug addicts.
In both cases, prison is used to solve the problem of the illegal nature
of the patient or addict’s behavior. The
therapeutic community is used to reeducate the patient or addict and health
administrators help to treat them.
Even the underlying intention in the management and
treatment of both kinds of patients is similar: managing and suppressing
derangement because derangement cannot be seen as an integral part of the
dominant values of society in a given historical moment. In the case of capitalistic society, every
kind of set-back to or decline in work productivity was seen as “abnormal” and
“ill”. The imposed way of understanding
“illness” (also understood as the form given to that illness) and the
“therapeutic instruments” used to treat illness were (and still are in part)
used to preserve the dominant social and economic system. Lunatic asylums,
shock treatments, malarial and insulin shocks, criminal lunatic asylums and the
excessive use of psycho-pharmaceuticals are just a few examples of how the
treatment of psychiatric patients was closely linked to the perpetuation of a
certain kind of imposed understanding of the illness. This particular kind of understanding of illness was useful to
the continued success of the dominant society.
However, the threat or setback to reproduction
represented by drug dependence is configured differently. This kind of threat is linked to
satisfaction gained outside of the goods of consumption and to the modification
of a state of consciousness. It is not
by chance that illegal drugs are those that can either create an altered state
of consciousness or a different route to pleasure. It is precisely this altered state of consciousness, or alternate
way to find pleasure, which the dominant society finds dangerous and
subsequently determines to be illegal. The
degree of dependency or toxicity of these illegal substances is not
important. Tobacco and alcohol (when it
is used as nourishment) are perfect examples of this.
The legal
definition of social danger was once automatically correlated with mental
illness in the legal code. The same
kind of definition, although not legally codified, can still be recognized in
relation to drug dependents. This
definition conditions the language and structure of the so-called “politics of
threat reduction.” This method of
treatment merely proposes to reduce the dangerous effects implicit in a drug
addict’s behavior by reducing the potential threat of an addict to himself or a
“healthy” society. The prescribing of substitutive therapies, such as methadone
for example, is not considered as a real therapy but rather as a tool to reduce
the damage of the addict.
This idea is also found at the base of the ambiguous
healthcare and welfare policy of the Jervolino-Vassalli law in Italy. Because of this policy, drug dependents are
tossed between jail, communities and public service organizations which are
often organized as a kind of “drug addict’s asylum.” It was only in 1994 with the Referendum Popolare that it was
possible to have a slightly more differentiated system of medical care. However, there are already attempts to
transform this policy.
It is clear that present day policies are not enough
to solve the problem of how we should treat drug addiction. Drug abuse and deaths caused by drugs are on
the rise. The prevalence of severe
viral infections is increasing and jails are overflowing with drug
addicts. The courts are jammed with
criminal and civil drug cases and large scale drug selling has been only
slightly diminished. Organized crime
continues to become richer and more powerful and to finance other legal and
illegal activities, such as arms trafficking.
Drug trafficking continues to be prevalent and crimes connected to drug
dealing are still a major problem. Although
available public funding to begin to solve these problems is, in fact,
considerable, positive results are very limited.
It is absolutely necessary to realize that there exist
specific needs and specific questions related to the resolution of these
problems. The mere repression of these
needs and questions is not effective and never was effective. Therefore, I believe that it is a social
duty to begin to consider alternative solutions.
I would like to make some analogies between
Prohibitionism and Anti-prohibitionism that may help to better explain the
Aprohibitionist point of view. On the political playing field, Prohibitionism
and Anti-prohibitionism are found on opposite sides. Anti-prohibitionism is to Prohibitionism as, on the economic
playing field, Free Trade politics is to Protectionism. Free enterprise (understood as the freedom
to achieve profit) can be thought of as an equivalent in the Market to the
freedom to take drugs. This is the
extreme liberal Anti-prohibitionistic point of view.
Just as anarchy can be understood as a form of
liberalism without a police state, so Anti-prohibitionism, brought to the
extreme, brings us to the thinking that “everything is permitted.”
The degree of Protectionism on the Market is more or
less parallel to the degree of Prohibitionism.
This parallel development proceeds until an absolute conception of the
ethical state is reached in which Protectionism and Prohibitionism reach their
most powerful expression.
The Anti-prohibitionistic and Prohibitionistic parties
are built based on the emphasis or importance given to the individual’s freedom
to fulfill one’s needs, to satisfy one’s desires and to have an answer to one’s
questions in order to allow civilization to prosper. The Prohibitionistic party believes that these needs and desires
must be more or less strictly controlled.
The Anti-prohibitionistic party believes in allowing the individual
freedom to pursue these goals.
At this point we have
reached an impasse. Enough antagonistic tension exists between these two
perspectives that each position can invalidate or disavow the other through a
number of equally legitimate arguments.
We have seen that in practice Prohibitionism has
failed. Anti-prohibitionism presents itself as a possible alternative, although
it is not the only or even the best alternative. In fact, it could be also a
dangerous alternative. Putting on the
market a type of goods that is freely sold means automatically placing that
goods into a logic of profit, a logic of sale and of increasing demand. It could possibly also mean spreading the
use of drugs and perhaps even displacing the profit from the clandestine seller
to the authorized one.
But Anti-prohibitionism is not the only possible
alternative to Prohibitionism. Anti-prohibitionism
represents the necessary opposition to Prohibitionism, the polarized example of
its opposite.
If we consider a dialectical perspective, a synthesis
mediating the two approaches could be considered. However, I believe that not even this approach is the best
solution, just as Critical Thought, which began with Hegel, by now is not
enough to elaborate the present phase of our social evolution.
A quality jump is needed, one that goes beyond the
antithesis, away from a synthesis and over the limits of both Prohibitionism
and Anti-prohibitionism.
What I propose is a perspective that is specifically
different from the above two positions, a point of view that distances itself
from them and at the same time strips them of their reasons for being and of
creating oppositions.
Therefore, I prefer to discuss APROHIBITIONISM, in
which a distancing from the previously discussed ways of thinking is already
evident in the meaning of the word
itself.
In practice, Aprohibitionism means devising a
different way of thinking that could be alternative to the Prohibitionistic and
Anti-prohibitionistic logic. Aprohibitionism means thinking about a procedure
that does not legalize goods in order to make them marketable. It means thinking about a procedure that
makes it possible to manage needs beyond merely repressing them or forcing
medical treatment but at the same time dealing with the possible increase in
supply. Aprohibitionism means thinking
about a potential use and therefore a worth for these goods that will not
become part of a value-based market. It
means stripping a commodity of its defining features, such as for example its
value in order to gain profit. This is
what I call a purification of the goods.
And thus makes possible the legality of that which remains outside of
the logic of production and reproduction, the worth of the goods, and tries to
avoid the risk of the increase of the use of drugs.
Thus, I consider it absolutely necessary to
differentiate these drugs based on their different levels of harmfulness. This differentiation should be determined by
the degree of dependence that the substance induces, the direct toxicity of the
substance and the degree to which one’s state of consciousness is altered while
under the influence of the substance.
According to this model, cannabis would be a substance
which, in my opinion, adults could freely grow for personal use. Along with this option or as an alternative
cannabis could be controlled by some form of state monopoly. A controlled state monopoly would be
accompanied by the distribution of information on the potential risks of
cannabis and there would be no form of promotion of the substance. Cannabis
could also be available for therapeutic use by medical prescription. The controlled administering of therapeutic
heroin, however, would be more appropriate for heroin addicts and would only be
for patients who were not able to undergo other therapies because they were
unsuccessful. Obviously, it is first necessary to ensure the availability of
other forms of therapies, such as, but not restricted to, substitutive
therapies. Although the depenalization
of the use of these substances is part of the Aprohibitionistic perspective, it
would be necessary to devise strategies of controlled recreational distribution
for substances that are very clearly harmful, such as alcohol, tobacco, ecstasy
and cocaine. A distribution of this kind should be organized as a state monopoly
(or clearly not for profit) and should be accompanied by adequate information
on education and prevention.
In conclusion, I present these ideas as proposals in
order to encourage further discussion. I
hope that I have been able to communicate what I mean by Aprohibitionism and
that, perhaps, it is an idea that may be applied not only to drugs.